Today is 3/14/15 — Super Pi Day — so was I telling my 7-year-old son all about the number
this afternoon. When I told him that
keeps on going forever and ever he asked “How do you know that?” Although I don’t know a proof that I could explain to a 7-year-old, I wanted to record the following proof which uses only basic calculus. It is essentially Niven’s famous proof, as generalized by Alan Parks, but I have tried to write it in a way which is more motivated than the usual treatments. As a bonus, the proof also shows that e is irrational.
Let be a positive real number. Our goal is to assume that
is rational and use this assumption to construct a continuous function
and a sequence of polynomials
for
with the following properties:
(1) and all
are positive on the interval
.
(2) There is a sequence of real numbers with
as
such that for each
,
for all
(3) The integral is an integer for all
.
To see why this gives a contradiction, note that (1) and (3) imply that for all
, but if
is the maximum value of
on
then (2) implies that
which is less than 1 for sufficiently large.
Let be the set of all continuous functions
on
with the property that both
and
are integers. Note that
is closed under addition, subtraction, and multiplication (it is what mathematicians call a ring).
We define to be the set of all
in
whose
derivative belongs to
for all
. The product rule for derivatives shows that
is closed under addition, subtraction, and multiplication, and by definition it is closed under taking derivatives.
Key Observation #1: If and
, then
for all
Proof: The proof is by induction on . The case
is trivial. Assume that
. We have
by assumption, and by the chain rule we have
. Since
and
is closed under multiplication, the result follows. Q.E.D.
We define to be the set of all
in
with a
antiderivative in
for all
More formally,
consists of all functions
in
such that for each
, there exists
in
whose
derivative is
. Note that by definition we in fact have
.
Key Observation #2: If and
is a polynomial, then
is an integer.
Proof: The proof is by induction on the degree of
. If
then
is constant, and the result follows easily from the fundamental theorem of calculus. Assume the result is true for polynomials of degree
. Letting
be an antiderivative of
in
and applying integration by parts, we obtain
which is an integer by the inductive hypothesis. Q.E.D.
We can now prove our main theorem, which as we will see implies that both and
are irrational.
Main Theorem: Suppose there is a function with
for
. Then
is irrational.
Proof: Assume for the sake of contradiction that with
positive integers. Then the function
belongs to
and satisfies
. (The derivative of
is
and its second derivative is
.) It follows from Key Observation #1 that
belongs to
for all
By Key Observation #2,
is an integer for all
. On the other hand, both
and all
are positive on
. Thus conditions (1) and (3) above are satisfied. To see that (2) is satisfied as well, let
be the maximum value of
on
. Then
, which goes to zero as
. As discussed above, conditions (1),(2),(3) together now lead to a contradiction. Q.E.D.
Corollary 1: is irrational.
Proof: Take and
. Q.E.D.
Corollary 2: is irrational.
Proof: Assume with
positive integers and take
and
. Q.E.D.
Concluding remarks
1. As mentioned in the introduction, this post is a reorganization and repackaging of the proof given in this article by Alan E. Parks, which originally appeared in the American Math Monthly. I first came across Parks’s proof in the book “Biscuits of Number Theory”, edited by Arthur Benjamin and Ezra Brown.
2. As Parks notes in his article, the main theorem easily implies the following generalizations of Corollary 1 and Corollary 2:
- If
and if
and
are both rational, then
is irrational.
- If
is a positive rational number then
is irrational.
3. The strategy of proof here is a very natural one. Every irrationality proof that I know of for or
involves reaching a contradiction by constructing a positive integer less than 1. And the argument used to bound the integral in (3) appears frequently (albeit in a different context) in analysis, especially elementary complex analysis. And the Key Observations, while clever, are simple consequences of the product rule for derivatives, the chain rule, and the fundamental theorem of calculus. So unlike other irrationality proofs that I’ve seen, I find this argument quite motivated. It is also accessible to anyone who has studied calculus and mathematical induction. And finally, it’s nice that the same argument proves irrationality of
and
at the same time.
Pingback: A p-adic proof that pi is transcendental | Matt Baker's Math Blog
Pingback: A motivated and simple proof that pi is irrational | A Shanghainese Student in America
I know that this is a slick way to prove that π is irrational. However, I’ve always been fond of the original concept behind Lambert’s proof, the idea being that tan(r) is irrational for r rational. This follows from the continued fraction expansion tan(r) = r/(3-r^2/(5-r^2/(7-r^2… .
The point here is that if r is rational, the the partial convergents of this continued fraction give rational numbers which converge too quickly to tan(r) for tan(r) to be irrational. Of course the proof requires some care, both to prove convergence of the continued fractions and to show the limit is irrational. But I like this approach because of the analogy with other irrationality proofs using continued fractions. A complete argument is given here: http://www.maths.unsw.edu.au/~angell/5535/chapter7.ps
Yes, Lambert’s continued fraction argument is also great! (And a similar analysis with tanh instead of tan proves that e is irrational, though of course this is a much easier fact than the irrationality of pi.)